[KB] "Deacon"-structing Burke Part Whatever

Edward C Appel edwardcappel at frontier.com
Tue Oct 28 16:34:47 EDT 2014


Greg,

A challenging and interesting post.  One quick take in opposition of a sort, though, pertains to the second-to- last paragraph:

Your notion of a non-negotiable, not-open-to-interpretation "sacred text" as a given in a genuine "religion" seems a bit too either/or.  Without such a text, you seem to be saying, religion desolves into philosophy.

The 250-year history of biblical criticism, both inside and outside of liberal Protestantism, and its effect on the very idea of a "sacred text" not open to various points of view and multitudes upon multitudes of interpretive schemes, runs counter to reality---unless we're going to prescind all thought of metaphysics---i.e., theology, "coy" or not--from the philosophy you speak of.  In other words, you seem to be requiring a definition of "religion," a transcendentalization of the "motive of perfection," that puts it in a straight jacket most actual religious liberals aren't bound by.

I wouldn't attempt to summarize this complex,critical, literary and historical account from Reimaris (1774-1778) to John Dominic Crossan (radical) and John P. Meier (more mainstream), both Roman Catholics by the way, both still publishing, and both treating the distinctively Christian documents in a most un-sacred way.  As even Meier has said, the New Testament exegete should treat the text as though being judged and interpreted by a Roman Catholic, a Protestant, A Jewish scholar, and an atheist, each having an equal vote.

This "demystification" or partial "demystification" of the texts of Judaism and Christianity has been standard fare in Mainline Protestant seminaries for decades upon decades, and surely has seeped into preaching and teaching in the Mainline denominations.

I wouldn't call them philosophical societies.

Also, by the way, Horace Bushnell, a Protestant preacher in Rochester, New York, published a book in 1849 that undercut the very idea of "language," creedal or biblical or whatever, as a vehicle for pristinely accurate, incontestable, and entire "truth."  Language just doesn't function that way, Bushnell claimed and argued.  This was about half a century before Burke was born.



Ed

             
--------------------------------------------
On Tue, 10/28/14, Gregory Desilet <info at gregorydesilet.com> wrote:

 Subject: Re: [KB] "Deacon"-structing Burke Part Whatever
 To: "Ed Appel" <edwardcappel at frontier.com>
 Cc: kb at kbjournal.org
 Date: Tuesday, October 28, 2014, 1:26 PM
 
 Ed—I take your point about Burke
 regarding fascism as a distortion or perversion of religion.
 To recall, he expresses it this way, “There is nothing in
 religion proper that requires a fascist state. There is much
 in religion, when misused, that does lead to a fascist
 state.” In other words, religion does not lead to fascism
 as day leads to night. But I would argue that the reason
 religion can, when misused, lead to a fascist state derives
 from the circumstance that both share the same metaphysical
 core. This metaphysical core is highly suspect with regard
 to its potential for benefiting human community. I know this
 statement will possibly seem outrageous at face value, but I
 make a detailed case for this view in a paper titled
 “Burke, Heidegger, Derrida, and the Specter of Nazism at
 the Origin of Rhetoric” (available online here: https://www.academia.edu/6400427/Burke_Heidegger_Derrida_and_the_Specter_of_Nazism_at_the_Origin_of_Rhetoric).
 
 Of course, this line of thinking features Burke’s
 sacrificial logic expressed in his phrase “cult of the
 kill” and all that he sees as bound up in that. The
 inevitability of this “logic”—what I identify as the
 metaphysical core—is what I take issue with in the above
 paper. When we start out with the “cult of the kill”
 metaphysical ground (and the late Burke seems to admit of no
 other alternative), we are not necessarily obliged to end up
 with the politics of fascism but we have necessarily greased
 the wheels in that direction. And human community all too
 often inclines in that direction when propelled by this
 metaphysical ground—which is in essence a logic of
 oppositional relation much like YES/NO computer
 gatekeeping—only where the YES/NO dichotomy is at the
 origin hierarchically conceived such that one side is, in
 its essence, superior to the other. This gatekeeping may
 work okay when making certain kinds of choices (though I
 would dispute this as well) but it does not work well when
 categorizing humans (leading to what Burke calls the logic
 of the sacrificial scapegoat). Alternative metaphysical
 ground, which Burke does not consider, leads to an
 alternative logic of gatekeeping whereby the essences on
 each side of the dichotomy are not hierarchically arranged
 at the assumptive origin. In this latter alternative
 metaphysical orientation, hierarchy among choices arises
 from a contextualized evaluative process, not a presumption
 at the outset.  
 
 This hierarchical “presumption at the outset” is another
 feature of what I regard as the metaphysical core of
 religion. It ties in closely with the notion of a “sacred
 text.” Here a “sacred" text may be defined as sacred
 only if it is divinely inspired or revealed. As such, it
 cannot be challenged or negotiated with. Most
 institutionalized religions center on sacred texts or texts
 that are made to be sacred. This notion of sacred texts
 flies in the face of everything communication scholars have
 learned about the nature of language—namely that it cannot
 be made to operate in ways that preclude interpretation
 (which may be seen as a form of negotiation). On this line
 of thought, any institutionalized religion that does not
 center on the notion of a sacred text effectively strays
 from religion into what may more properly be called
 philosophy—an approach to life where argument and
 negotiation prevail over revelation and certainty. 
 
 Interestingly, Burke’s “cult of the kill” thesis is,
 therefore, in many ways inconsistent with the more
 interpretive view of language he offers in, for example,
 Permanence and Change. However, Burke seems to be of two
 minds when it comes to his views on the nature of language.
 His later work in “Fact, Inference, and Proof in the
 Analysis of Literary Symbolism,” for example, offers a
 view of language more consistent with the sacred text notion
 of language (where the notion of “fact” substitutes for
 the notion of “sacred text”). I find this inconsistency
 in Burke troubling along with what I view as his blindness
 to the above mentioned metaphysical alternative orientation.
 
 
 Greg
 
   
 On Oct 28, 2014, at 7:55 AM, Edward C Appel <edwardcappel at frontier.com>
 wrote:
 
 > Greg,
 > 
 > Thanks for the link.  I'll give the interview a
 listen and get back.
 > 
 > Two things:
 > 
 > First, Deacon is not one of the plagiarizers of Burke's
 thought.  He has told me he knows nothing about Burke,
 and I believe him.  Deacon is, after all, in two fields
 not noted for Burkean connections, anthropology and
 neuroscience.  I've been forwarding to Deacon my kb
 posts.  After the most recent one, he got back to me
 with near assurance he wants to start reading Burke. 
 It's actually more confirming, I believe, that these
 similaries in theory, philosophy, and conclusions from
 research appear independently---especially from a
 significant source in a hard science.
 > 
 > Second, as I read it, the connection Burke makes
 between Hitler's fascistic rants and religion in "Hitler's
 'Battle'" is offered to the detriment of Hitler, not
 religion.  Burke calls what Hitler has done a
 "bastardization" of religious rhetoric, meaning, in Burke's
 typically elliptical way, an illigitimate use of the motive
 of perfection, a taking-to-the-end-of-the-line his depiction
 of this arbitrary and quite earth-bound, untranscendent
 scapegoat, whose demise will supposedly '' +"cure" the ills
 of the German people.
 > 
 > This harks back to what Burke says in ATH about
 "heroic," tragic-frame rhetoric approaching "coxcombry" when
 employed for nonreligious reasons.  God and the devil
 are "perfected" conceptions, or can be so idealized.
 > 
 > Now, this does not mean given expressions of religion,
 like Islam today in various formulations---in terms of its
 fanatical quest to make its earthly environment confirm
 exactly to its extreme, and one can say I think, socially
 and historically backward standards---are not
 facistic.  Nor is it to say that fundamentalist
 religion of any kind, even when thoroughly
 transcendentalized, isn't to be "discounted" for language as
 a source of conceptual excess.  "Perfection" of
 whatever variety, when grimly pursued in respect to the
 here-and-now or the graat beyond, is to be taken  with
 salt and viewed with suspicion, Burke surely hints at, if
 not in each case clearly proclaims.
 > 
 > Religion in general is not the customary "enemy" in
 Burke's writings.  More frequently, it's the immanent
 expressions of that "theological" motive in the "quest for
 empire" in this world that earns Burke's strongest disdain.
 > 
 > That's my sermon for today.  As the Stage Manager
 isn Our Town said, "Twan't much."
 > 
 > 
 > 
 > 
 > Ed
 > 
 > 
 > --------------------------------------------
 > On Mon, 10/27/14, Gregory Desilet <info at gregorydesilet.com>
 wrote:
 > 
 > Subject: Re: [KB] "Deacon"-structing Burke Part
 Whatever
 > To: "Ed Appel" <edwardcappel at frontier.com>
 > Cc: kb at kbjournal.org
 > Date: Monday, October 27, 2014, 3:08 PM
 > 
 > You make a good case, Ed, for
 > Deacon’s debt to Burke. Hopefully he will eventually
 have
 > something more to say about that. 
 > 
 > Speaking of unacknowledged “debt” to Burke, I came
 > across a YouTube video recently in which Hamed Abdel
 Samad
 > is interviewed. It seems he wrote a controversial book
 on
 > what he calls “Islamism.” In the interview he
 explains
 > the connection he makes between religion and
 fascism—a
 > connection Burke also makes in his 1938 review of
 Hitler’s
 > Mein Kampf. Exploring this connection is indeed
 > controversial but Samad makes an interesting case of
 it.
 > And, Ed, in doing so, he seems to follow certain
 aspects of
 > our line of argument about conflict management in our
 > Rhetoric of the Enemy article. Here is a link to the
 video:
 > 
 > 
 > https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=jCfp48c31u0
 > 
 > Greg
 > 
 > 
 > On Oct 21, 2014, at 3:36 PM, Edward C Appel <edwardcappel at frontier.com>
 > wrote:
 > 
 >> Burkophiles,
 >> 
 >>     I want to summarize what I
 see as
 > fifteen or so points of intersection between Burke’s
 > dramatism/logology and Terrence W. Deacon’s semiotic
 > theory.  I do so in no particular order. 
 I’m
 > basing my assessments on Deacon’s most recent book,
 > Incomplete Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter, and
 three
 > of his academic articles or book chapters: “The
 Symbol
 > Concept,” “The Emergent Process of Thinking as
 Reflected
 > in Language Processing,” and “Beyond the Symbolic
 > Species.”  Seven times so far, I’ve posted
 here on
 > Deacon at some length.  I’ll make reference to
 the
 > dates of those postings, or a few of them, where you
 might
 > find further treatment, when appropriate.
 >> 
 >> 1.    Deacon’s notion of an
 > “absential feature” in human symbolic action, as 
 >> well as in whatever we want to call the
 nonsymbolic
 > activity of the “lower animals,” echoes Burke’s
 > primary emphasis on the “negative” as author and
 > motivator of the human drama.  This “absential
 > feature,” as extant in the “Creatura,” but not in
 the
 > “Pleroma” (Deacon here borrows language from the
 ancient
 > Gnostics by way of his mentor Gregory Bateson), is the
 > elephant in the living room scientistic theorists
 > recurrently ignore in their efforts to reduce
 anthropology
 > to biology, biology to chemistry, chemistry to
 physics.
 > 8/7/14.
 >> 
 >> 2.    From this absential feature at the
 > core of the “entelechy” that 
 >> characterizes beings in the Creatura (yes, Deacon
 > references Aristotle and the Four Causes), a list of
 > ancillary features built around “purpose” and
 reflective
 > of Burke’s pentad emerges.  See Deacon’s
 analogous
 > idea of “teleodynamics.”  8/7/14, 8/9/14.
 >> 
 >> 3.     Deacon, like Burke,
 > claims that action, so to speak, cannot be reduced 
 >> to motion, phrasing the concept somewhat
 differently
 > from Burke.  For Deacon, it’s the absential
 feature
 > itself that eludes the scientistic rationale. 
 “There
 > are no components to what is absent,” he emphasizes.
 > 8/7/14.
 >> 
 >> 4.    Deacon’s definition of what a
 > symbol is and is not appears to mirror 
 >> well enough Burke’s conception.  I say seems
 to
 > mirror “well enough” because Burke does not as
 carefully
 > exclude, or even much refer to, mathematical, signal-
 or
 > code-like, computational-type “symbols.” 
 Deacon
 > argues convincingly that math-type “symbols” do
 not
 > possess the airy abstractiveness, web-like relatedness
 to
 > and embeddedness in, a whole lexicon of terms none of
 which
 > can be “mapped” in relation to objects in the real
 > world, a “system-internal web of relationships”
 > requiring “an associated indexical operation  .
 . .
 > in order to point outside this system.” 
 Neither
 > Melia’s book chapter “Scientism and Dramatism:
 Some
 > Quasi-Mathematical Motifs in the Work of Kenneth
 Burke”
 > (The Legacy of Kenneth Burke), nor Burke’s references
 to
 > the “statistical” in PLF, seem to undercut this
 claim.
 >> 
 >>     To put the matter simply:
 In the
 > lingo of dramatism, numerals in themselves do not
 exude
 > “drama” (make exception for the indirect, the
 > derivative), whereas the words, phrases, and sentences
 of
 > the world’s conventional, arbitrary languages do. 
 > That’s the implicit lesson Deacon’s semiotics would
 tend
 > to highlight. 9/16/14.
 >> 
 >> 5.    Deacon’s conception of the
 > origins of language sounds a lot like Burke’s 
 >> speculations in those QJS articles (1952/1953),
 > reprinted in LASA (pp. 419-79).  Deacon speaks of
 “an
 > undifferentiated starting condition.”  “We
 must
 > ask: What’s the form of a thought”---or “the idea
 that
 > a sentence conveys”---“before it is put into
 words,”
 > the “’mental images’ not quite formed or desires
 and
 > intentions to achieve some imagined goal only vaguely
 > formulated?”  These “embryos of a speech
 act”
 > would be “focused on aiming for and achieving
 expressive
 > goals.
 >> ”
 >>     For Burke, those
 “expressive
 > goals”---“connotative,” “suggestive,”
 > “loaded,” “fraught . . . with significance”;
 I’m
 > deep into Roget’s here---might stem from a
 > “’pre-negative’ . . . tonal gesture,”
 “calling
 > attention-to “ “danger” with “sound[s] . . .
 > hav[ing] a deterrent or pejorative meaning” (LASA,
 pp.
 > 423-24).  Deacon’s “lexicality,” a
 pre-linguistic
 > “pointing to” would serve as basis for this
 transition
 > into morally-tinged negation of the kind that
 > “dramatically” invests the danger or opportunity
 in
 > question with quasi-theological import.  The
 negative
 > as “engine of intentionality” with its
 now-infinite
 > vistas (indeed, now “rotten with perfection”),
 would
 > begin to indict as well as beckon, accuse as well as
 > highlight, come upon its denizens with an aura of
 spiritual
 > hazard, as well as material consequence. 9/16/14.
 >> 
 >>     Deacon does refine his
 description
 > of this likely lengthy transition with: “I see this
 > particular near universal [the “oral-vocal”] to be
 a
 > relatively late emerging biological adaptation for
 symbolic
 > communication.”  The “gestural embodiment”
 > probably came first, since our primate ancestors were
 not
 > good at vocality.  The vocal came to predominate
 > because of its greater potential for myriad “sign
 > vehicles.”
 >> 
 >> 6.    Which brings us to Burke’s
 > hexadic acknowledgement of “attititude” as 
 >> an ingredient in the symbolic mix, language
 primarily
 > expressing an attitude, creating an orientation toward
 > certain pathways of action, giving cues to action and
 a
 > command to follow those cues.  For Deacon, that
 > attitudinal, “expressive” dimension is denominated
 a
 > “mood.”  In respect to symbolic origins,
 “Within
 > this frame of social communicative arousal,” he
 maintains,
 > “what might be described as the ‘mood’ of the
 speech
 > or interpretive act is differentiated.” 
 “This
 > ‘mood’ needs to be maintained.”  It’s
 “a
 > focused readiness and expectation with respect to
 social
 > interaction.”
 >> 
 >> 7.     Burke famously defines
 > humans as the “symbol-using animal.” 
 >> Deacon’s “symbolic species” functions as a
 > virtual synonym.  “In my work,” Deacon says,
 “I
 > use the phrase symbolic species, quite literally, to
 argue
 > that symbols have literally changed the kind of
 biological
 > organism we are.”
 >> 
 >>     “Indeed, there is ample
 evidence
 > to suggest that language is both well-integrated into
 almost
 > every aspect of our cognitive and social lives, that
 it
 > utilizes a significant fraction of the forebrain, and
 is
 > acquired robustly under even quite difficult social
 > circumstances and neurological impairment.  It is
 far
 > from fragile.”
 >> 
 >>     “So rather than merely
 intelligent
 > or wise (sapient) creatures, we are creatures whose
 social
 > and mental capacities have been quite literally shaped
 by
 > the special demands of communicating with
 symbols.  And
 > this doesn’t just mean that we are adapted for
 language
 > use, but also for all the many ancillary mental biases
 that
 > support reliable access and use of this social
 resource.”
 >> 
 >>     This defining human trait
 or
 > attribute gets locked in globally via “the near
 universal
 > regularities of human language.”
 >> 
 >> 8.    “Drama”---or, to put it more
 > logologically, “theological drama”---as 
 >> master “screen,” through which even the
 > “positives of nature are seen through the eyes of
 moral
 > negativity”?  Howabout Deacon’s
 approximation:
 > “We are ‘symbolic savants,’ unable to suppress
 the
 > many predispositions evolved to aid in symbol
 acquisition,
 > use, and transmission . . . . We almost certainly have
 > evolved a predisposition to see things as symbols,
 whether
 > they are or not.”  E.g., “the make-believe of
 > children,”  “find[ing] meaning in
 coincidental
 > events,” seeing “faces in the clouds,”
 “run[ning]
 > our lives with respect to dictates presumed to
 originate
 > from an invisible spiritual world.”  “Our
 special
 > adaptation is the lens through which we see the world.
 
 > With it comes an irrepressible predisposition to seek
 for a
 > cryptic meaning hiding beneath the surface of
 > appearances.”
 >> 
 >>     An approximation? 
 Sounds more
 > like a paraphrase.  Always take note of “our
 special
 > adaptation” and factor it into our interpretations
 of
 > “reality.”
 >> 
 >>     More later, I hope, by way
 of
 > additional intersections between Burke and Deacon.
 >> 
 >> 
 >>     Ed
 >> 
 >> 
 >> 
 >> 
 >> --------------------------------------------
 >> On Thu, 10/9/14, Edward C Appel <edwardcappel at frontier.com>
 > wrote:
 >> 
 >> Subject: Re: [KB] "Deacon"-structing Burke Part
 > Whatever
 >> To: kb at kbjournal.org
 >> Date: Thursday, October 9, 2014, 5:05 PM
 >> 
 >> Burkophiles,
 >> 
 >>      Let me reiterate, clarify,
 > emphasize:
 >> It’s the dyadic grammatical pairing of subject
 and
 >> predicate that Deacon says is not “innate” in
 the
 > human
 >> mind and human discourse, as in Chomsky’s
 universal
 >> generative conception, not the “symbolic”
 faculty
 >> itself.  No evolutionary, genomic, or
 > neurological
 >> evidence exists for Chomsky’s view.  It’s
 > mostly
 >> implicit in these shorter works by Deacon, but
 > strongly
 >> implicit, that symbolization itself does come
 naturally
 > to
 >> the Symbolic Species.  That is, you’ll
 recall,
 > the
 >> title of his earlier book.
 >> 
 >>      You may wonder, too, at the
 > claim that
 >> children pick up on their own a facility for
 indexical
 > and
 >> combinatorial modes of symbolic reference, rather
 than
 > learn
 >> that culminative syntax from the structures of the
 >> conventional language into which they’re
 socialized.
 > 
 >> The fact is, Deacon asserts, “The infant already
 >> ‘knows’ the logic of these ‘rules’ of
 >> indexicality,” which bring noun subject and
 verbal
 >> predicate together.  Those necessary
 regularities
 > are
 >> well absorbed the first year and a half by way of
 > experience
 >> itself.
 >>     
 >>      Also, as he or she reads him,
 a
 > Burkean
 >> might be taken aback by Deacon’s occasional
 reference
 > to
 >> the “predicate frame” (the “comment” on
 the
 >> “subject” or “topic” that requires the
 careful
 >> “indexing”) as the “symbolic” part of a
 >> “complete” sentence or iteration.  This
 does
 > not
 >> mean, for Deacon, that the noun subject and object,
 or
 >> referential parts, of the fully-formed utterance
 > hasn’t
 >> been symbolically transformed by the symbolizing
 >> species.  Even proper names, which, unlike
 common
 >> nouns, can be indexically “mapped” a la
 Saussure,
 > are
 >> still embedded a culturally conventional,
 > artifactualized
 >> linguistic system.  What Deacon seems to be
 > suggesting
 >> here is that distinctive symbolization
 “emerges”
 > from
 >> nonsymbolic indexicality—the “pointing”
 gestures
 > and
 >> vocalizations of lower animals that indicate some
 > recognized
 >> “icon” that poses danger, potentially
 satisfies
 >> appetite, requires territorial markings or
 >>   signals of aggression or
 subservience,
 > etc.---distinctive
 >> symbolization emerges especially via an
 > “expressive,”
 >> “mood”-generating, “sense”-making,
 meaningful,
 >> ultimately abstractive vocalization that
 characterizes
 > how
 >> to conceive of, proceed toward, exploit, or
 retreat
 > from the
 >> object or being so referenced.  As Burke has
 > said,
 >> “The true locus of assertion is not in the
 DISEASE,
 > but in
 >> the STRUCTURAL POWERS by which the poet
 encompasses
 > it”
 >> (PLF, p. 18, emphasis not added), a redemptive
 >> “act”-centered predication.
 >> 
 >>      So, there seems to be an
 > underlay of the
 >> presymbolic in the indexical not so present in the
 >> nonindexical.
 >> 
 >>      Constraining indexicality
 > Deacon
 >> anatomizes into four aspects, only one of which
 I’ll
 >> mention here, the most basic, what he calls
 > “semiotic
 >> constraints.”  These manifest themselves in
 >> “predication constraints (symbols must be bound
 in
 > order
 >> to refer)”; “transitivity and embedding
 > constraints
 >> (indexicality depends on immediate correlation and
 >> contiguity across the transitive)”; and
 > “quantification
 >> (symbolized indices need re-specification).
 >> ” 
 >>      In elaboration, Deacon says,
 > “To state
 >> this hypothesis in semiotic terms: a symbol must
 be
 >> contiguous with the index that grounds its
 reference
 > (either
 >> to the world or to the immediate agreeing textual
 > context,
 >> which is otherwise grounded), or else its
 reference
 >> fails.  Contiguity thus has a doubly
 indexical
 > role to
 >> play.  Its contiguity (textually or
 pragmatically)
 > with
 >> the symbolizing sign vehicle [see paragraph 3
 above]
 > points
 >> to this symbol, and their contiguity in turn points
 to
 >> something else.  This is an expression of one
 > further
 >> feature of indexicality: transitivity of
 reference.”
 > 
 >> Or, more “simply stated, a pointer pointing to
 > another
 >> pointer pointing to some object effectively
 enables
 > the
 >> first pointer to also point to that object.”
 >> 
 >>      Ultimate grounding in the real
 > world
 >> seems vital to Deacon for complete and satisfying
 >> predication.
 >>     
 >>      Being the neuroscientist that
 > he is,
 >> Deacon asks, by way of “transitivity” as he
 calls
 > it,
 >> “How does this interaction between phases of
 > sentence
 >> differentiation produce anything?  What sort
 of
 > signals
 >> are being sent in each direction” from one area
 of
 > the
 >> human brain to another?  To simplify,
 what’s
 >> happening is “counter-current information
 > processing”
 >> that generally proceeds from “lower” to
 > “higher”
 >> structures of the brain, and from back to
 front---from
 >> limbic, peri-limbic, and peripheral, to
 > “specialized”
 >> cortical regions; from “posterior
 > (attention-sensory)
 >> cortical systems” to “anterior
 (intention-action)
 >> cortical systems”; i.e., from reptilian brain
 > structures
 >> like the thalamus, hippocampus, and amygdala, to
 the
 >> advanced cerebral components of mammalian,
 primate,
 > and
 >> early hominid ancestry.  And, of equal
 importance,
 > back
 >> again, from “higher” to “lower,” etc., as
 >> well.  These “counter-current”
 >>   electro-chemical operations afford
 a kind of
 > monitoring,
 >> provide checks and balances, generate
 > “equilibrium.”
 >> 
 >>      Whether we’re neurologically
 > examining
 >> sensory, or motor, or cognitive, or linguistic
 > operations,
 >> they all look pretty much the same, I interpret. 
 > They
 >> each exhibit similarly “emergent”
 characteristics,
 > in
 >> terms of evolutionary origins and current
 sequential
 >> functioning.
 >> 
 >>      What remains to be dealt with
 > is a
 >> summary of the complementary intersections between
 > Burke’s
 >> dramatism/logology and Deacon’s semiotics, and
 also
 > the
 >> challenge Deacon possibly poses to Burke’s
 > action/motion
 >> dichotomy.
 >> 
 >>      At a later date.
 >> 
 >>      And a P.S.  If you object
 > to my use
 >> of the singular form of the verb “to be” in
 the
 > “what
 >> remains” sentence, do read the Fowler-Nicholson
 >> “Dictionary of American-English Usage,” pp.
 >> 374-75.  Fowler and Nicholson don’t explain
 it
 > well,
 >> but they do get it right, unlike billions of
 > publications
 >> I’ve read, including the New York Times. 
 I’m
 > still
 >> a grammarian of a kind at heart, even after the
 >> Deacon-struction.
 >> 
 >> 
 >>      Ed     
 >    
 >>           
 >> 
 >> --------------------------------------------
 >> On Mon, 10/6/14, Edward C Appel <edwardcappel at frontier.com>
 >> wrote:
 >> 
 >>   Subject: Re: [KB]
 "Deacon"-structing Burke Part
 > Whatever
 >>   To: kb at kbjournal.org
 >>   Date: Monday, October 6, 2014,
 3:34 PM
 >> 
 >>   Burkophiles,
 >> 
 >>       I’ve already said
 >>   that Terrence W. Deacon’s
 semiotic theory
 > partly
 >> supports,
 >>   partly enhances, and partly
 challenges Burke’s
 >>   dramatism/logology, in my
 view.  Burke
 > surely, we would
 >>   maintain, enhances Deacon, as
 well.  Before
 > I get to the
 >>   “challenge”---as the song
 goes, “Don’t
 > know where,
 >>   don’t know when”---let me add
 to the themes
 > of support
 >>   and enhancement.  Here I’ll
 be
 > referencing, in
 >>   particular, two of Deacon’s
 shorter works, the
 > journal
 >>   article, “The Emergent Process
 of Thinking as
 > Reflected
 >> in
 >>   Language Processing,” and
 Deacon’s book 
 > chapter,
 >>   “Beyond the Symbolic Species,”
 The Symbolic
 > Species
 >>   being the title of the
 > anthropologist/neuroscientist’s
 >>   tome that preceded Incomplete
 Nature: How Mind
 > Emerged
 >> from
 >>   Matter, about which I previously
 bloviated.
 >> 
 >> 
 >>       I would judge
 Deacon’s
 > explanatory
 >>   “god-term”/”rome-term” to
 be
 > “emergent,” as
 >> per
 >>   the title of the here-featured
 treatise. 
 > The word
 >>   “emerge” plays a similar role,
 I think, in
 > “Beyond
 >> the
 >>   Symbolic Species.”  All
 roads seem to lead
 > from
 >>   “emerge”/”emergent” to the
 two sets of
 > dialectical
 >>   opposites subsumed below:
 >> 
 >>       The primary polar
 matchup term
 >>   “emergent” is pitted against,
 is
 > “innate,” as in
 >> the
 >>   pre-processed,
 genetically-programmed and
 > “engineered”
 >>   universal generative grammar of
 Noam Chomsky and
 > his
 >>   epigoni.  No evidence of such
 a special
 > facility can be
 >>   found in the human genome or in
 the structures of
 > the
 >> human
 >>   brain, which actually look not
 that much
 > different from
 >>   those found in a mouse, let alone
 a
 > chimpanzee.  (I’m
 >>   referencing Incomplete Nature as
 well as
 >> “Emergent.”) 
 >>   We have here a “process of
 coming out,” a
 > “rising .
 >> .
 >>   . out of a surrounding medium,”
 even “an
 > effect
 >> produced
 >>   by a combination of causes but
 unable to be seen
 > as the
 >> sum
 >>   of their individual effects”
 (The Shorter OED),
 > except
 >>   through careful, detailed scrutiny
 of the natural
 > history
 >>   and evolution of living organisms,
 pathways of
 >>   electro-chemical discharge in the
 brain, the
 > very
 >> neurology
 >>   of sensory, motor, thinking, and
 linguistic
 > development
 >> and
 >>   outcomes,
 >>    animal communication generally,
 >>   even the listening and reading, as
 well as the
 > speaking
 >> and
 >>   writing, of symbolizers like
 us---all these
 > operations
 >>   recapitulating the same sequential
 steps. 
 > (It’s
 >>   appropriate here to note what
 Susan Greenfield
 > and
 >> Christof
 >>   Koch, both neuroscientists, said
 in an exchange
 > in
 >>   Psychology Today: Electrochemical
 discharges in
 > the brain
 >>   can occur within time frames of
 1/14th of a
 > second.)
 >> 
 >>       From this
 dialectical
 >>   emphasis on “emergent” rather
 than
 > “innate,” there
 >>   is derived the contrasting
 concepts of
 >>   “subject/predicate.” 
 They assume more
 > independent
 >>   “roles,” if not do
 “battle” with each
 > other,
 >>   seemingly asymmetrically, in a way
 that Chomsky
 > would not
 >>   likely entertain. 
 “Subject/predicate”;
 > “noun
 >>   phrase/verb phrase”;
 “”topic/comment”;
 >> “indexical
 >>   support/predicate frame”;
 > “’pointing’”/desired
 >> or
 >>   undesired result; “orientation
 component”/act
 > to
 >>   accomplish in respect to that
 “orientation”;
 >>   “function,” as in
 > functionary/”argument”;
 >>   “reference/sense”;
 “indexical
 > operation/symbolic
 >>   operation”; “slots” for
 “pointing,” or
 >>   “addresses”/”operation”;
 “(embedded)
 > bound
 >>   indexes/symbolic operation”;
 > “disambiguating” the
 >>   “indexical”/successful
 “symbolic” action
 > toward a
 >>   desired end---these serve as
 various expressions
 > of the
 >>   “process” of
 >>    “emergence,” left to
 >>   right, in communication, part of
 which, the
 >>   “indexical”-founded-on-the-“iconic”
 > preliminaries
 >>   I’ve already spoken of, homo
 loquax/dialecticus
 > shares
 >>   with other living creatures.
 >> 
 >>       The major point
 Deacon makes is,
 > there
 >>   is no built-in
 genetic-neurological template by
 > which the
 >>   symbolic species gets from subject
 to
 > predicate.  That
 >>   aptitude, that enabling
 juxtaposition, resides
 > not in our
 >>   biology, nor in our cultural
 conditioning. 
 > It is a
 >> faculty
 >>   humans learn in early childhood
 via the bound and
 > required
 >>   “logic” of successful
 symbolization. 
 >>   “Disambiguating”
 indexicality---i.e.,
 > “:pointing”
 >>   via gestures or indexical words to
 what it is we
 > are
 >>   symbolically talking about---is a
 requirement
 > for
 >> successful
 >>   human communication.  We must
 put those two
 > communicative
 >>   elements together somehow to get
 what we’re
 > after, or
 >> tell
 >>   others more or less accurately
 what we want them
 > to
 >> know. 
 >>   Nonsymbolic animals have no such
 indexical
 > problem,
 >> because
 >>   their communication doesn’t get
 beyond the
 > “iconic,”
 >>   the “:arousal” to
 “attention” a
 > significant
 >>   “form” will evoke for
 them---and the
 > “indexical,”
 >>   the gestural or
 >>    vocal “pointing” to
 >>   that feared or desired object. 
 > “Symbolization” via
 >>   predication complicates,
 potentially, actually
 >> practically,
 >>   interrupts, erects barriers in
 succession to
 > making clear,
 >>   what we are talking about, who or
 what we have in
 > mind,
 >> what
 >>   we want others to “do” in
 order for our
 > interests to
 >> be
 >>   satisfied.
 >>           
    
 >>       How human thinking,
 sensory and
 > motor
 >>   skills, and language production
 get to happen
 > involve
 >>   similar, if not identical, neural
 continuities.
 >> 
 >>       And how all this
 >>   dovetails so nicely with Burke’s
 dramatistic
 > philosophy,
 >>   yet broaches an issue Burke may
 not have
 > adequately dealt
 >>   with, remains.
 >>    
 >>       Next
 >>   time.
 >> 
 >> 
 >>       Ed  
 >> 
 >> 
 >>   --------------------------------------------
 >>   On Tue, 9/16/14, Edward C Appel
 <edwardcappel at frontier.com>
 >>   wrote:
 >> 
 >>    Subject: [KB] "The
 >>   Symbol Concept"
 >>    To: kb at kbjournal.org
 >>    Date: Tuesday, September 16, 2014,
 > 1:08 PM
 >>    
 >>    Burkophiles,
 >>    
 >>        Thanks, Bob, for your
 >>   response on Burke,
 >>    rhetoric, and
 >>   “repetition.”  I hope to
 get back on
 >> 
 >>   that one later.
 >>    
 >>        I
 >>   posted a few weeks ago on Terrence
 W.
 >> 
 >>   Deacon’s book Incomplete Nature:
 How Mind
 > Emerged from
 >>    Matter.  I said, in effect, and
 > sought to
 >>   briefly
 >>    summarize how, Deacon’s
 >>   philosophy of language part
 >>    supports, part
 >>   enhances, and part challenges
 Burke’s
 >> 
 >>   dramatism/logology.  Ronald
 Soetaert of
 > Ghent U.
 >>    seconded that take on Deacon’s
 > relevance to
 >>   our
 >>    enterprise.
 >>    
 >>        Since then, I’ve been
 > in further
 >>    dialogue with Professor Deacon. 
 > He sent me
 >>   three of
 >>    his published articles, then
 >>   later, a fourth, later still an
 >>    essay now
 >>   in press.  Two of these
 pieces have to do
 >> 
 >>   with his mentor, Gregory Bateson,
 whose work I
 > referred
 >>   to
 >>    in at least one of my posts as being
 > a
 >>   clear precursor of
 >>    Deacon’s semiotics. 
 >>   The other of those first three,
 >>    an
 >>   encyclopedia chapter entitled
 “The Symbol
 > Concept,”
 >>    I’d like to summarize in this post
 > and maybe
 >>   one or two
 >>    more.  The chapter appears in
 >>   The Oxford Handbook of
 >>    Language Evolution
 >>   (Oxford University Press,
 2011).  If
 >> 
 >>   you’re interested, please read
 on.
 >>    
 >>        (And as you read, do
 > keep in mind
 >>   that
 >>    Incomplete Nature has made a profound
 >>   impact, judging from
 >>    multiple reviews
 >>   easily accessed on the internet.)
 >>       
 >>        First, Deacon’s
 > confirmation of
 >>   Burke,
 >>    formerly unbeknownst to Deacon, as I
 >>   noted: Deacon’s in
 >>    anthropology and
 >>   neuroscience, not communication
 and
 >> 
 >>   literature, the prime sources of
 Burkean interest
 > and
 >>    scholarship.  From the
 > perspective of
 >>   Incomplete
 >>    Nature, I pointed out how
 >>   Deacon’s critique of the
 >>    commonplace
 >>   “scientific lens,” maybe
 epitomized by
 >> 
 >>   behaviorism’s notion of the
 human mind, any
 > “mind,”
 >>   as
 >>    a “black box” we ought to
 > prescind
 >>   from our motivational
 >>    calculations, is
 >>   faulty and inadequate.  Input
 and
 >>    output,
 >>   neural stimulus and response,
 reduction of mind
 > to
 >>    biology, then to chemistry, then to
 > physics,
 >>   are the
 >>    requisite foci for useful data and
 >>   explanation, so much of
 >>    hard science, at
 >>   least, seems to suggest. 
 Deacon says
 >>    no,
 >>   we have to factor in, indeed
 highlight, a
 > necessary
 >>    “absential feature”(similar to
 > Burke’s
 >>   negative) that
 >>    becomes the basis for human
 >>   purpose, trial and error---we
 >>    can genuinely
 >>   label it all the
 >>     aspects of “action,”
 >>   expressive of a chosen
 >>    “preference,”
 >>   that cuts across “spontaneous”
 causes
 >> 
 >>   in nature and orients persons
 toward “work”
 > that
 >>   limits,
 >>    organizes, directs life
 >>   outcomes.
 >>    
 >>        “The
 >>   Symbol Concept” further
 >>    underscores the
 >>   dramatistic relevance of
 Deacon’s
 >> 
 >>   thought.  Deacon once again
 takes issue with
 > regnant
 >>    scientific/technological
 terminologies
 > that
 >>   confuse what a
 >>    “symbol” actually is. 
 >>   A symbol is not, Deacon
 >>    claims, mere
 >>   “code,” “sign,”
 “icon,” or number,
 >>    that is, symbols are not mere
 pointers
 > ,
 >>   markers, gauges, or
 >>    portraits of the kind
 >>   so often denominated
 >>    “symbols.” 
 >>   Actual “symbols” refer,
 abstractly
 >>    and
 >>   generally, “irrespective of any
 natural
 >> 
 >>   affinities.”  In other
 words, as per
 > Burke, symbols
 >>    synthesize, synthetically, disparate
 > beings,
 >>   entities, or
 >>    events for seemingly
 >>   pragmatic, culturally-conditioned
 >>    purposes
 >>   that transcend mere appearance of
 similarity. 
 >>    Contra Saussure (with the exception
 of
 > proper
 >>   nouns),
 >>    symbolic reference cannot be
 >>   “mapped.”  To the
 >>    extent that a common
 >>   word or symbol “maps”
 anything, it
 >> 
 >>   “maps” a position in a given
 lexicon in
 > relation to
 >>    other
 >>     terminologies in that
 >>   symbol system.
 >>    
 >>        The
 >>   airy, diaphanous character of
 >>    Burke’s
 >>   equivalent notion of symbolic
 action/reference
 >>    finds peak expression in his chapter,
 > “What
 >>   Are the Signs
 >>    of What?---A Theory of
 >>   Entitlement.” in LASA. 
 There
 >>    Burke
 >>   maintains what he said in the
 Grammar about how
 > common
 >>    symbols refer to “nothing” in the
 > real
 >>   world, only here
 >>    he follows up with how
 >>   “reference” is reversed, in
 terms
 >>    of
 >>   customary suppositions: “Things
 are the signs
 > of
 >>    words,” rather than vice
 > versa.  In so
 >>   “latching
 >>    on” to the symbol’s
 >>   concept, so to speak, tangible
 >>    entities and
 >>   “objects” “materialize”
 the
 >> 
 >>   “spirit” of the symbol,
 participate in its
 >>    “pageantry” (pp. 361, 379).
 >>        
 >>        But---and
 >>   here’s where Deacon gets into
 >>    semiotic
 >>   and semiological issues foreign to
 Burke’s
 >>    dramatism, i.e., the
 “enhancement”
 > I
 >>    mentioned---“sign”-age,
 >>   “signal”-ing,
 >>    “code”deciphering,
 >>   the whole gamut of concepts
 related
 >>    to
 >>   computer algorithms and
 “encryption,” come to
 > bear in
 >>    undergirding the higher-order
 > cognitive
 >>   process we call
 >>    human symbolic
 >>   communication.  Like love and
 marriage
 >> 
 >>   (for the traditionally minded,
 anyway), you
 > can’t have
 >>   one
 >>    without the other.  The symbols
 > of
 >>   human language are
 >>    fashioned out of sounds
 >>   and written or printed characters
 >>    the roots
 >>   of which are presymbolic, and
 prehuman, for that
 >>    matter.  Such “iconic” and
 >>   “indexical” sources
 >>    of communication
 >>   are evident in the activites of
 nonsymbolic
 >> 
 >>   animals, as well as in the
 “symbolic actions”
 > of you
 >>   and
 >>    me.  Thus, add “iconism” and
 >>   “indexicality” to
 >>    Deacon’s
 >>   “absential feature” and
 Bateson’s
 >> 
 >>   “difference that makes a
 >>     difference”
 >>   (that results from some
 pre-ethical sense of
 >>    negation, and occasions a form of
 > “trial and
 >>   error” in
 >>    the service of a kind of
 >>   “preference,” a capacity for
 >>    which all
 >>   living things show signs of
 possessing and
 >> 
 >>   utilizing).
 >>    
 >>        In
 >>   explaining this “hierarchy”
 of
 >>    notions
 >>   he uses in explaining how human
 symbolic action
 >>    works, Deacon borrows from the
 > philosophy of
 >>   Charles Sanders
 >>    Peirce.  Peirce coined the
 >>   term “legisign” to refer
 >>    to iconic,
 >>   indexical, and symbolic signs in
 general. 
 >> 
 >>   The locution “sinsign” refers
 to a specific
 > instance
 >>   of
 >>    an iconic or lexical sign (there can
 > be
 >>   no such thing,
 >>    actually, as a “symbolic
 >>   sinsign,” as will become clear,
 >>    I hope. 
 >>   “Natural affinities”
 characterize
 >> 
 >>   sinsigns; not so, anything that
 attains the level
 > of
 >>    “symbolic,” based on, as Burke
 and
 > Deacon
 >>   say,
 >>    arbitrary, conventional, culturally
 >>   reflective origins of
 >>    reference.)  A stick
 >>   figure drawing on a restroom door
 >>    is an
 >>   iconic legisign.  It
 “portrays” in
 >> 
 >>   general.  A picture of a
 famous person is an
 > iconic
 >>    sinsign.  It portrays in
 > particular.  A
 >>   smoke
 >>    alarm sound is an indexical legisign,
 >>   as is the position of
 >>    a needle on a
 >>   pressure gauge.  They
 “point” or
 >> 
 >>   orient
 >>     toward an action in the
 large.  A
 >>   particular smell of
 >>    smoke is an indexical
 >>   sinsign.  Spoken or written
 >>    words, in a
 >>   syntactical context or not, are
 symbolic
 >> 
 >>   legisigns.  The reference is
 to “a general
 > concept or
 >>    type of object.”
 >>    
 >>        Proper names might seem
 > to be a bit
 >>   like
 >>    symbolic sinsigns, but they are not. 
 >>   Their reference
 >>    can be mapped, one-to-one
 >>   Saussure-like, but “the
 >>    sign-vehicle is a
 >>   conventional form.” 
 Therefore
 >>    Peirce
 >>   would call them “indexical
 legisigns.” 
 >>    “Dolphin signature whistles are
 > indexical
 >>   sinsigns”
 >>    (Deacon, e-mail message,
 >>   9/9/14).  Symbolic signs of
 >>    the most
 >>   abstract or merely potential kind
 of reference
 >>    Peirce calls “qualisigns.”
 >>    
 >>        Symbolic reference,
 >>   then, functions like
 >>    this: “A written
 >>   word [for instance] is first
 recognized
 >>    as
 >>   an iconic sinsign (an instance of
 a familiar
 > form), then
 >>    an indexical legisign (a type of sign
 > vehicle
 >>   contiguous
 >>    with other related types), and
 >>   then as a symbolic legisign
 >>    (a conventional
 >>   type of sign referring to a
 conventional
 >> 
 >>   type of reference).
 >>    
 >> 
 >>       Deacon employs the
 text message
 > “smiley
 >>    face” and Aristotle’s take on how
 > a
 >>   “signet ring”
 >>    functions in
 >>   communication as examples of this
 hierarchal
 >>    progression in the production of
 > meaning for
 >>   symbol-users,
 >>    one of Deacon’s most
 >>   salient points being: This
 >>    “dependency of
 >>   symbolic reference on indexical
 reference
 >> 
 >>   [and iconic reference]” mirrors
 the dependency
 > of human
 >>    symbolic action/communication on the
 >>   “genetic,” even
 >>    “phylogenetic,”
 >>   capacities for iconic and
 indexical
 >> 
 >>   communication of a sort in
 “living organisms”
 > in
 >>    general, a theme of Deacon’s (and
 >>   Bateson’s) I
 >>    emphasized in my previous
 >>   posts on Incomplete Nature.
 >>    
 >>        So, for further review
 > and/or
 >>   comment:
 >>    
 >>        What do
 >>   Deacon’s semiotic distinctions,
 >>    and
 >>   especially unifications, mean for
 Burke’s
 > signature
 >>    “(Nonsymbolic) Motion/(Symbolic)
 > Action”
 >>   dichotomy 
 >>    (1978/2003)?  Is some sort of
 >>   modification in order
 >>    along the lines of
 >>   Jim Chesebro’s complaint that
 Burke did
 >> 
 >>   not pay enough attention to
 nonsymbolic motive s
 > (Burke
 >>    panel at the ECA Convention, 1992)?
 >>    
 >>        Does Deacon’s
 >>   critique of Chomsky’s
 >>    Universal
 >>   Generative Grammar as the innate
 > “constraint”
 >>    on syntactical linguistic
 > relationships in
 >>   human
 >>    communication, in favor instead of
 >>   “indexical”
 >>    constraints, tend to
 >>   support Burke’s notion of the
 >>    negative as
 >>   “the engine of intentionality”
 and the very
 >>    dawn of human symbolism
 > (1952/1953/1966)?
 >>     
 >>        Maybe something on
 >>   those issues later.
 >>    
 >>    
 >>        Ed
 >>        
 >>    ”
 >>             
   
 > 
 >>    
 >>            
 >    
 >>    
 >>    
 >> 
 >>   _______________________________________________
 >>    KB mailing list
 >>    KB at kbjournal.org
 >>    http://kbjournal.org/mailman/listinfo/kb_kbjournal.org
 >>    
 >> 
 >>   _______________________________________________
 >>   KB mailing list
 >>   KB at kbjournal.org
 >>   http://kbjournal.org/mailman/listinfo/kb_kbjournal.org
 >> 
 >> 
 >> _______________________________________________
 >> KB mailing list
 >> KB at kbjournal.org
 >> http://kbjournal.org/mailman/listinfo/kb_kbjournal.org
 >> 
 >> 
 >> _______________________________________________
 >> KB mailing list
 >> KB at kbjournal.org
 >> http://kbjournal.org/mailman/listinfo/kb_kbjournal.org
 > 
 




More information about the KB mailing list